> [!Definition] Definition (logical validity)
> An [[Argument]] is *logically valid* iff there is no possible situation in which its premises are all true and its conclusion false.
>
> In other words, an argument is logically valid iff it's conclusion is a [[Logical consequence|logical consequence]] of its premises.
> > *Negation*. An argument is logically invalid iff it has a [[Counterexample]].
> [!NOTE] Definition (for formal language)
> 1. A [[L1P (Propositional Logic)|propositional logic]] argument is ***logically valid*** iff in joint truth table for all its premises and conclusions there is no row in which its premises are all $T$ and its conclusion $F$.
> 2. An argument is ***valid in virtue of its truth functional form*** iff it has a [[Sentence#^efade4|truth functional]] form that can be captured by an $L_{1p}$ argument which is ***logically valid***. (We can say that it is TT-valid).
> [!info] Note
> - Every argument that is valid in virtue of its truth functional form is also valid in the general sense.
> - Not every valid argument is valid in virtue of its truth functional form.
>
# Example
> [!Example]
> Suppose $P,Q$ are $L_{1p}$ sentences then the following argument is logically valid:
>| $P$
>| $\lnot P$
>|----
>| $Q$
> [!Example] Example
> | $P \lor Q$
> | $P$
> |---
> | $(Q\lor \lnot Q)$
>
>> In general, if the conclusion of an argument is a [[Sentence#^e8f9c8|tautology]], that argument is logically valid.